Fighting For Ourselves: Anarcho-Syndicalism and the Class Struggle (from this point on
referred to as FFO) is an important contribution to existing introductory anarchist works
and an essential read for those aiming to familiarise themselves with both historical and
contemporary anarcho-syndicalist thought and practice. The book stands as a testament to
the seriousness with which the authors treat their ideas and it is to their credit that
the text is available both so cheaply as well as orientated towards all levels of
readership1. The book far outstrips, also quite dated now, comparable works, for example,
Rocker?s classic Anarcho-Syndicalism: theory and practice which crucially due to its date
of publication is unable to draw lessons from anarcho-syndicalism?s seminal episode ? the
CNT during the Spanish civil war.
FFO, however, as a work of anarchist theory falls short of expectations and misses a
number of opportunities to answer more robustly the challenges facing revolutionary
organisations in the 21st century as well as longstanding criticisms of the authors? own
tradition.
Achievements: Overview
The book does succeed in its aims to ?recover? a unique, international history of class
struggle. Sections concerning the syndicalist, councilist and anarcho-syndicalist
traditions of France, US, UK, Spain, Germany and Argentina are lively and engaging. These
form a solid introduction to common ideas, methods and lessons that are otherwise
scattered or misrepresented in more conventional texts. Part of this history includes the
events of France, May 1968 and Italy 1969 which is refreshingly not filtered via the
narratives of any particular ideology as is so often the case with these heavily contested
episodes (this presents certain issues as well to be discussed further below). Here the
authors take the more constructive approach of outlining key events from the perspective
of the participants who made them so important ? the wildcat actions of autonomous workers
- as well as emphasising the critical role of the trade unions played in de-mobilising
this section of the movement.
Many of the studies are brought up to the present period and in respect to this it would
also have been useful to have seen a bit more reflection on the existing IWW (Industrial
Workers of the World), particularly in respect to its place as the other contemporary
syndicalist tendency operating within the British labour movement. It is possible to infer
a certain standpoint from the authors? criticism of ?apolitical? or neutral syndicalism
but this is not made explicit through these passages. The revisiting of the writings of
Pouget is also particularly insightful and a valuable opportunity to encounter what is an
often neglected figure of this tradition within the English-speaking world.
The history of the Labour party builds on the already sound analysis of ?Labouring in
Vain? (published by the Manchester-based libertarian communist journal Subversion)
complimented by a critical account of the development of the welfare state, which as Adam
Ford notes in his review for the Commune2, has the strength of emphasising the consensus
across political party lines within the post-war government for reform. The way that
social reforms have been used to de-mobilise and effectively curb the aspirations of
working class movements in the UK is a critical point and should be made more often. In
fact the key elements of the social democratic consensus are covered well throughout the
book. A little more consideration could have been given to how ?spatial fixes? for worker
militancy extended into alternative management regimes outside of capitalism?s economic
centres and the way these are instrumentally used to stabilise global economic
accumulation3. Irrespective of this, the case of the partial, transitory and temporal
nature of the Keynesian/social democratic project ? spanning 25 years in only a small part
of the world - is well made.
Equally well-crafted is the ?myth-busting? approach to the neoliberal counter-revolution,
particularly in debunking the notion that neoliberalism is necessarily anti-union. As the
authors note the object of neoliberal policy is to ensure workplace order and this can be
achieved by a variety of means including successful co-option of the trade union movement.
This is as well as outlining the strategic fashion in which this new political and
economic consensus was formed and drawing the important conclusion that, ?neoliberalism
constitutes class collaboration on an individual basis?; a conclusion which opens up a
number of opportunities for further analysis in light of the conditions of the ongoing
crisis and the disappearance, as the authors also note, of the economic basis of this
individualised class collaboration (in the form of accessible home ownership and the
extension of easy credit4).
Criticisms: Overview
Our criticisms of the book relate, in many ways to the particular peculiarities of the
Anglophone tradition of anarchism. While many of the more valuable sections of the book
build from a carefully considered, often quite innovative socioeconomic analysis, the
sections concerning theory are generally representative of a certain superficial attitude
towards the tradition itself (with the exception, perhaps, of the treatment of Pouget).
The strategic conclusions that are drawn by the authors in the concluding chapter and the
kind of challenges and lessons outlined prior to this are not drawn together in a way that
makes these strategic choices speak to the most important aspects of the analysis. Overall
the book gives the impression of anarcho-syndicalism as an almost contingent theory of
struggle ? based on continuing experiments in workers? self-organisation not the conscious
theorisation of militants ? rather than a theory and practice ready to meet the challenges
of the 21st century. Important changes within the tradition itself ? such as the authors?
endorsement of ?minority unionism? ? are often discussed unsatisfactorily and leave a
number of traditional criticisms of anarcho-syndicalism partially or inadequately addressed.
We also have to take issue with the way that certain ideas outside of the
anarcho-syndicalist tradition are represented throughout the book, particularly anarchist
communism but also workerism and (the non-representation of) autonomism and the
situationists. These are accounts often supported by distortions of the source texts or
exaggerations of certain unfavourable aspects of their history. This is as well as
questioning the particular way that the histories of some movements are treated, most
notably that of the Federaci?n Obrera Regional Argentina (FORA) ? the Argentine Regional
Workers? Federation.
Overall we have to criticise the authors? choice of methodology in terms of how they treat
their recovered history. The authors? view of anarcho-syndicalism as ?trial and error
around a political economic core? may be true in a broad sense but doesn?t really do
justice to the level of theorisation and strategies practised by members of these
movements themselves. This treatment gives the impression, as is discussed in more
particular detail below, of a series of cultural and historical factors that shaped the
experiments of an international movement, often seemingly predestined to fail in light of
the influence of these conditions. This is a method far more reminiscent of the historical
determinism of Marxist history than of libertarian writings.
Finally while the authors introduce an important theoretical tool in the identification of
the ?associational? and ?representational? role of the trade unions we feel that this
needs to be augmented by a fuller analysis of the role of unions within capitalism. This
would at least be partially remedied by a more thorough discussion of the structures of
capitalism and the state that also condition the sale and purchase of labour power, this
is however unfortunately largely absent within the book.
The ?associational? and the ?representational?
Central themes that are returned to throughout the book are the ?associational? and
?representational? functions of unions. This later develops into a broader criticism of
the way the political and economic functions are separated out in representational unions
and leads into the authors? argument for the benefits of an associational,
political-economic union. The ?associational? aspects of unions are defined as the following,
Quote:
?That of an association of workers, joining together for a common purpose (whatever that
may be). In other words, the union is the means by which workers relate to one another.
That relationship may be horizontal or hierarchical, usually voluntary but, as in the case
of ?closed shops? where workers have to join the union, sometimes compulsory. Their
association may be long-lasting as in today?s trade unionism, or more transient as in the
early, pre-amalgamation unions.?
(FFO, p.12-3)
This is separated from the ?representative? functions of unions in relation to capital;
Quote:
?This usually means management, but sometimes includes politicians and the state, should
they decide to intervene in a dispute ... The representative function carries with it
certain assumptions. Firstly, it is premised on the legitimacy of the existence of social
classes. Secondly, in order to gain the right to negotiate on workers? behalves,
representative unions tend to jettison any explicit politics which could turn off
potential members, since size becomes an important factor in determining their place in
the TUC pecking order.?
(FFO, p.13)
The authors make clear that, ?both of these functions become closely intertwined in the
course of the historical development of the trade union movement? (FFO, p.13).
The associational and representational categories offer a good means to systematise our
understanding of what communists find both desirable and problematic within existing
workers? organisations. Trade unions are, for example, for the most part spaces that bring
together workers on the basis of a shared interest and, therefore, a possible means of
also bringing about a political convergence on class issues5. However by focusing too
strongly on this dynamic alone the authors risk simplifying the character of unions and,
at worst, giving the impression of unions as a halfway house between revolution and reform.
As Marx highlights in his analysis of the struggles over the working day (Capital, Vol. 1,
chapter 10) the association of workers can follow as much the logic of capitalist
competition as it does point to a world beyond it. A union, for example, is a pretty sound
economic investment for workers on the basis of their need to preserve their sole
commodity ? labour power ? from diminishing via the extreme rates of exploitation of
capitalists. This is entirely consistent with the social logics which follow from the
circuits of capital and doesn?t necessarily imply any communistic ideas or practices on
the part of workers. The ability for workers to bring labour power to the market is
essential to their continued survival. Association can present a means for ensuring this
particular interest of workers is defended ? their ability to continue to sell their
labour power in the future, against, for example, unsafe working practices which will
damage or shorten their working life ? without ever necessarily challenging the class
system that compels workers to sell their labour in the first place. These are the far
deeper contradictions which communists have to tackle in respect to trade unions. While
association may allow for a space for tendencies toward communism to flourish ? usually as
workers start to realise the internal limits of their demands within capitalism ? its
intermediate function is ultimately to facilitate the sale and purchase of labour power.
It is true that both the associational and representational functions exist as
contradictory forces within unions. Also that a union?s ?associational? functions are
those most closely associated with the pre-conditions of communist practice, i.e. free
association, non-hierarchy, equality. It is also true that there is a constant tendency
within capitalism for unions to adopt representational functions due to their
compatibility with the needs of capitalist management. Nonetheless even associational
means of negotiating within capitalism are still just that ? the negotiation of terms
within capitalism. In other words, even horizontal, ideologically anti-capitalist unions
have to conform to the logic of capitalism and operate by the law of surplus value. It may
be difficult, to use the example in the text, for the boss to negotiate with a stadium of
workers but when pushed to extremes capitalism will do just that6. This is not, of course,
to reject the day-to-day struggle of workers as hopelessly reformist or conservative.
Rather it is to point to a particular set of contradictions that all communists have to
navigate irrespective of the union?s form. As stated above the issue is about locating
within these where the tendencies towards communist practice can develop.
The point here is to suggest a wider analysis - in terms of the role of the essential
function of trade unions within capitalism as means of negotiating the sale of labour
power - that goes beyond the associational and representational functions. Such a
perspective helps to clarify both what is at stake between these two organisational forms
as well as the ultimate limitations of both as models of working class organisation within
capitalism.
In the absence of such an analysis, ?association vs. representation?, and the case of
political-economic organisation over political and economic organisation, risks taking the
form of an ahistorical maxim presented as a catch-all answer to why all prior
organisations have failed. This is also not aided by the inadequate way in which
hierarchy, political authority and the state are treated throughout the book. There are a
few largely unqualified references to the role of the state in text, for example, that
?the state serves capitalism and cannot be served to serve the interests of the
proletariat? and that winning the prize of political power means ?getting to manage
capitalism?. However the role of the state as, for example, the representative of the
interests of collective capital or even the socioeconomic basis of political authority is
inadequately qualified. Assertions such as ?when you capture the state, the state also
captures you? risk presenting a rhetorical objection to authority reminiscent of our
tradition in immaturity as opposed to the more systematic, historical materialist analysis
provided by Kropotkin, Bookchin and others.
What results is a formalist conception of revolutionary practice that in spite of the
richness of the social and economic analysis throughout the book (and even crucial
insights relating to the influence of social and economic conditions on the shape of
movements) ultimately boils down to the need for a single ?correct? formula of
revolutionary organisation. The theme of the political-economic organisation does go some
way to addressing the issue of both the form and content of organisations. In other words,
that organisation does not just require an associational structure but also needs to
promote specific ideas. The missing issue, however, is how these should relate to changing
levels of class consciousness. In other words how organisation forms a dynamic
relationship to changing social and material conditions within the class. A fairly
straightforward case is made in the closing chapter of the radicalising effect of struggle
and that through this the workers will be brought closer to the politics of the
anarcho-syndicalist union. This is, however, pretty unidirectional and there is not much
consideration of what the function of the union should be should struggles ebb or subside.
Other than that it should look to initiate new ones.
Looking specifically at the nature of class consciousness gives clearer answers of why the
contradictions which the authors identify ? of the dominance of representation over
association and the separation of the economic and political ? continue to recur beyond
the explanations given of the cultural, historical lineages and organisational errors
associated with certain movements. The authors fail to answer in a comprehensive fashion
why we witness the separation of economic and political functions, representation over
association as recurrent phenomenon within working class organisations (Marxist, anarchist
and reformist) over the past century.
For example in the case of explaining the CNT?s participation in the republican government
the authors put forward a convincing case of the critical importance of the strategic
choices available to CNT activists on the eve of the revolution, the contradictory nature
of Spanish anarcho-syndicalism and limitations imposed by geographical isolation and fear
of foreign intervention. There are a number of further issues that could have also been
taken up here7. Nevertheless a central purpose of this analysis is to counter the
criticisms of Malatesta (discussed in greater detail below) that mass membership of unions
will generally lead to a reformist slide of the politics of the union. Malatesta?s
criticisms are rightfully identified as an important reference point for the distinction
between anarchist communists and anarcho-syndicalists and recur in the commentary
throughout the book. The authors correctly argue that it was actually the rank-and-file,
mass membership that was, more often than not, the more radical force during the
revolutionary period. This would appear to invalidate the criticism that formal openness
necessarily brings about reformist unions. The political-economic and revolutionary
character of the CNT is favourably compared to the purely economic nature of the, for
example, reformist CGT.
It is accurate to state that CNT militants at the rank-and-file played a leading role in
the fight for collectivisations and against the politics of the Popular Front over this
period. Yet their action would have been insignificant were it not for the fact that the
ranks of the organisation were also swelled over this period by millions of radicalised
peasants and workers. The most inspiring practices of the revolution, in short, arose as
the result of the collaboration of revolutionary currents within the CNT and the
constructive actions of thousands of peasants and workers. How then to unpick the puzzle
of the critical influence of this largely new section of the membership?
The answer is provided not just by looking to the programme and actions of the CNT but
also close study of the growing composition and class consciousness of the Spanish working
class. It was this which proved to be decisive in shaping the fate of the revolution in
the period leading up to and during the revolution. It also provides a better account of
why ? with the working class faced with the de-mobilisation of the republic as well as the
limits placed on collectivisations by the CNT itself ? the civil war stopped having a
social revolutionary character before the military defeat of the CNT. The revolutionary
character of the CNT?s mass membership over this period was entirely contingent on the
heightened state of consciousness of the working class. The CNT both extended and placed
limits on the growing consciousness of the class over this time but it was the action and
mentality of the workers which was decisive.
The question, in sum, is not solely an issue of representation vs. association or the
economic vs. the political-economic but how these functions form a dynamic relationship to
the changing aspirations and consciousness of the class. It was the positive correlation
of all three of these things which put the CNT in such a fortuitous position on the eve of
the revolution, an important conclusion that can likewise be drawn in terms of the success
of the Bolsheviks twenty years earlier.
Representation of anarchist communism
There are two issues in respect to the representation of the anarchist communist tradition
within FFO. The first is in the portrayal of anarchist communist ideas as being infused
with a ?humanist? concern, and as a result the (erroneous) claim that, ?the tradition put
a varying emphasis on the class struggle as either a progressive or regressive force?
(FFO, p.30). This informs how the ideas are represented throughout. The second is how
Malatesta?s particular views on syndicalism are treated throughout the book.
The primary source for the ?humanist bent? of anarchist communism is a rather cursory
remark made by the social historian Damier cited from his introduction to
anarcho-syndicalism. While Damier has provided an invaluable and sweeping study of
anarcho-syndicalism over the 20th century his knowledge of anarchist communism is
comparably lacking and it is misplaced to draw such a strong view from a work that is not
principally concerned with anarchist communism8. Identifying a humanist tendency within a
much broader, history of libertarian socialist thought may be fair, if this was to include
for example early utopians such as Morris. The tradition most clearly understood as
anarchist communist however (also that which corresponds to the figures in the text) are
those ideas developed from the experience of the First International. Here the
characterisation of a ?humanist bent? and a shifting position on class is entirely misplaced.
In support of this interpretation the authors provide a quote from Malatesta, taken from
his speech at The International Anarchist Congress (Amsterdam, 1907), in which he appears
to refute the existence of classes and class interests. This is however both a
misrepresentation and misinterpretation of Malatesta?s views. His particular choice of
words withstanding, the meaning of his position has to be properly contextualised in terms
of the debate in which it formed a part. His statement that, ?there are therefore no
classes in the proper sense of the term? is made to challenge the economicism of Monatte
and Monatte?s belief that the class struggle was a sufficiently politicising force in
itself9. He is not claiming that there are no social classes or class interests, this
would be contrary to almost all his views up to this point, but of the non-existence of
class as a distinct political grouping within capitalist society (what Marx would identify
as the contrast between the class ?in itself? and ?for itself?). In fact, if you return
the passages from the original quote that the authors chose to remove the correct meaning
is fairly clear (I have italicised the returned sentences);
The basic error of Monatte and of all revolutionary syndicalists, in my opinion, derives
from an overly simplistic conception of the class struggle. It is a conception whereby the
economic interests of all workers ? of the working class ? are held to be equal, ]whereby
it is enough for workers to set about defending their own particular interests in order
for the interests of the whole proletariat against the bosses to be defended. The reality
is very different, in my view. The workers, like the bourgeoisie, like everyone, are
subject to the law of universal competition that derives from the system of private
property and that will only be extinguished together with that system. There are therefore
no classes, in the proper sense of the term, because there are no class interests. There
exists competition and struggle within the working ?class?, just as there does among the
bourgeoisie. (Malatesta quoted in Antonelli, 1907: 123)
It is possible to challenge Malatesta on the basis that perhaps he bends the stick too far
here in terms of not acknowledging the possibility of a positive, sociological class
identity within capitalism, but this would be entirely different from bringing the class
basis of his analysis into dispute.
Kropotkin is likewise subjected to the quite lazy and common misrepresentation that it was
his evolutionary theories that motivated his anarchism and not his activities within the
popular classes. This is a view that is, unfortunately, repeated quite frequently within
the anarchist movement and needs to be tackled more decisively. It is necessary to stress
that this is completely at odds with Kropotkin?s actual activity during his lifetime. He
had an incredible impact on the rise of revolutionary anarchism, not least in terms of
being a central figure in winning the movement away from collectivism and mutualism to the
ideas of libertarian communism10. Incidentally this also included, despite initial
reservations and views eventually very close to Malatesta11, an enthusiastic endorsement
of the burgeoning syndicalist movement later in his life;
Quote:
For Kropotkin, revolutionary syndicalism represented a revival of the great movement of
the Anti-authoritarian International which the Marxists were effectively trying to destroy
at the congresses of the Second International by directing it into parliamentary channels
just as they had done at the Congress of Basle in 1872 ... In his message to a meeting in
London of delegates from British and French unions in 1901 he called for 'an International
Federation of all Trade Unions all over the world' where workers would 'support each other
irrespective of political opinions and nationality in the direct struggle of labour
against capital?.
(Cahm, 1989: 268)
During this period he also laid the groundwork for the principles of a ?maximalist?
revolutionary syndicalism, ideas very close to that which were later taken up by the FORA
(Cahm, 1989: 241).
Such a view also doesn?t really correspond to the legacy he left in terms of his writings.
Reference to Kropotkin?s seminal work ? Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution ? come at the
expense of sidelining the more rigorous, historical studies present in The State: Its
Historic Role, The Conquest of Bread and Ethics among others. They also misunderstand the
purpose of the work. Mutual Aid is often cited as a key reference point for a liberal,
humanistic anarchism12. Kropotkin?s intention, however, was not to lay some naturalistic
basis for anarchist ideas but to put forward an anarchist critique of the social Darwinism
prevalent during his lifetime. Both its character, and common misreadings, are actually
very close to those associated with Marx?s Capital. For while Marx?s intention to form an
internal critique of the dominant ideas of bourgeois political economy spawned its own
?worldview Marxism?13, replete with its own absolute laws, Kropotkin?s critique has
spawned its own (admittedly far less pernicious) ?ethical anarchism?.
Ultimately it also does disservice to both the ideas and reputation of both Malatesta and
Kropotkin to suggest they had such wavering views on issues that earned them both periods
of imprisonment and exile.
This is not to say that some of the particular characteristics identified by the authors
of the early anarchist communist movement are altogether inaccurate. In its infancy the
tradition did at times move at odds to the wider labour movement. Part of this related to
the difficulties of developing means for influencing workers actions beyond those areas
already monopolised by the statists and reformists. The avocation and practice of
terrorism also, although more the responsibility of individual groups than those
associated with the traditions of the International, had a further effect in isolating the
movement. This was sometimes initiated in response to state suppression but not
exclusively so. Even then this was generally not at the expense of focus on more communal
and collective forms of agitation. Nonetheless the lessons to be drawn from the turn to
insurrectionalism are important and are sadly lacking in the authors? account which
erroneously attributes the failure to gather mass support from a disinterest in organised
labour.
It would be more accurate to say that where disagreements concerning the unions did occur
it was more in relation to whether syndicalism was a sufficient organisational force or in
need of something more. Whether syndicalism was simply a means or a means to an end; this
was and still is a central point of differentiation with respect to the anarchist
communist and anarcho-syndicalist tradition.
This was also a central issue upon which the debate between Malatesta and Monatte hinged.
The authors correctly attribute the importance to Malatesta?s views here and they recur
throughout the analysis in the book. The examples of the organisational evolution of the
FAUD and the CNT (covered above) are also cited as counter-examples to his thesis that
open, mass unions will tend towards reformism. Both these are not quite fair to
Malatesta?s original case as, particularly in the instance of the FAUD, these unions took
on a radically different function quite distinct from the particular examples that his
views were related to. For example in the case of the FAUD the authors cite that its
continuing success related more in its ability to act as a minority force catalysing other
struggles than as a formally open union per se. Irrespective of this the authors?
commentary gives the perception that these criticisms relate to some desire to maintain
?anarchist purity?14. This is not exactly representative of ? what we would characterise
as - the ?organisational dualist? or specifist position Malatesta expounded.
Malatesta?s views were far closer in spirit to that of Bakunin?s ?International
Brotherhood? and the Intimit? Internationale ? a proposed and later, real clandestine
network of dedicated revolutionaries, the latter of which ending up exercising
considerable ideological influence on the Anti-Authoritarian International (Black
International). Whatever one should think of the necessity of the clandestine basis of
such an organisation, its purpose was not to exercise or enforce an ?anarchist purity? but
to draw together the best lessons and practices of the tradition amongst revolutionaries.
This was not an exercise in ideological doctrine but conceived as a tool for intervention
within ongoing struggles15. This acknowledged the necessity of propagating a libertarian
communist programme while also understanding that setting the conditions of membership of
the workers? organisations as ideologically anarchist was also to drastically limit their
appeal. The specifist organisation was an attempt to introduce those workers radicalised
by struggle in the intermediate organisations (unions and fraternal societies) to the
ideas of anarchist communism. This was in contrast to the views of Monatte, who viewed
syndicalism as sufficiently anarchist in itself, and the anarcho-syndicalists, who argued
that the intermediate organisations themselves should be infused with an anarchist programme.
Representation of workerism
Italian Marxist currents of the 1960s (commonly collectively referred to as workerism or
Operaismo) are subject to a similarly poor representation in the book. The authors?
account, as stated above, of the events of Italy 1968 themselves is reasonably
comprehensive. This has the novelty of also drawing in both the internal (in terms of the
influence of reformism and limited scope of tactics) and external (in terms of the actual
gains available within capitalism over this period) limits that came to shape the form of
the labour movement over this period. Hence we get a clearer sense why in Britain ? where
there was a traditional dominance of partnership trade unionism and radicals operated a
?dual-card? or ?boring from within? strategy ? this period of heightened militancy
culminated in the ?Winter of Discontent? whereas in Italy and France workers practised
more imaginative actions.
There is fair discussion of the restricted scope of workerist ideas within the continued
legacy of Leninist ideology. The treatment considering the current?s decline, however, is
unfair and the passage quoted from Wright (FFO, p.82-3), in particular, stresses the
re-emerging influence of the trade unions as much as an ideological turn towards the armed
struggle in terms of attributing cause to the decline in workplace influence16. Citing
Wright to support a broader claim of workerism?s link to the rise of the urban guerrilla
groups is completely unrepresentative of the research presented his book. It simplifies
the more complex picture that he presents of a diversity of groups, individuals and
tactics and the context of the turn to the armed struggle in terms of an increasingly
violent campaign of repression pursued against workers by the Italian state as well as the
expectation of a fascist coup (Wright, 2002: 150). It also fails to acknowledge the often
suspicious relationship between Potere Operaio and the first generation of Brigatte Rosse,
that the workerist endorsement of ?militarisation? was almost entirely ideological in
nature and even then carried with it strong criticisms of the ?subjectivism? practised by
the urban guerrillas (Wright, 2002: 151)17. Likewise that it was the ability of the state
to exploit just such confusion between the practices of the urban guerrilla groups and the
workerist?s endorsement of ?mass armed struggle? which allowed key figures such as Negri
to be charged and publicly vilified as ?mastermind? of the Aldo Moro kidnapping in spite
of the fact that, according to the testimony of a Brigatte Rosse leader, ?he had nothing
to do with the Red Brigades?18.
Such a simplistic account of the decline of workerism similarly pays no acknowledgement to
the evolution of these ideas into the mid-1970s and the birth of autonomism and the ?area
of autonomy?. This misses the important lessons drawn from the translation of direct
action in the workplace into the community in the practice, for example, of
?self-reduction? (the collective refusal to pay heightened utility or transport bills) ? a
movement which was able to mobilise 180,000 families in the Piedmont region of northern
Italy and enjoyed practical support from the Comitati Autonomi Operai (Workers? Autonomous
Committees) at the state-controlled electricity commission who were able to restore power
to those disconnected for defying rate rises (Wright, 2002: 158). Out of the ?area of
autonomy? also came a growing network of ?free radios? which formed a counter-propaganda
network to the growing mass media of the corporations and state. These movements are
important to consider because they suggest the opening up of new areas of resistance
within the reconfigurations of advanced capitalism as well as pointing to areas of
mobilisation beyond the more limited scope of the shop floor. It likewise reflects poorly
on the authors? conclusion that the legacy of this period was mostly the ?politicisation?
(recuperation) of militants.
This failure to exploit the excellent opportunity that the history of this movement gives
to re-assess and expand the framework that the workerists provide ? particularly in
respect to what it could tell us how syndicalist methods could relate to the community ?
is only worsened by all but cursory references, e.g. taking ?control of the streets? (FFO,
p.107), to community organisation throughout the book. Such a focus not only reproduces
ableist and patriarchal blind-spots, in neglecting those terrains of struggle that do not
occur primarily on the shop floor19, but also lends itself to a familiar criticism of
anarcho-syndicalism as an ultimately narrower vision of social anarchism unwilling to
acknowledge the debt that it owes to its own ?communal dimension? (see Bookchin, 1993).
Historical Methodology
The conclusion to the sections devoted to the episodes of May 1968 and Italy 1969 are,
ultimately, quite fatalistic. This is a historical methodology in evidence throughout the
book. Having established that a mass, revolutionary union movement could not have emerged
out of the turmoil and social democratic compromise following World War II the authors
argue that its failures can be attributed to the absence of just such a revolutionary
union movement during these episodes. In light of this one is forced to be drawn to the
conclusion of the impossibility of revolution at this time. Especially considering how it
is hard to see how the prescribed political tasks;
Quote:
?to generalise strike movements, to counter the efforts of the trade unions and political
parties to return to normal, and to spread militancy between and beyond workplaces into
wider society.?
(FFO, p.84-5)
were really that far beyond what anarchists, workerists, situationists (another ignored
current in the book) and other revolutionary elements were both advocating and doing at
the time. Ultimately we are given no indication of how a revolutionary union would have
fared better ? in spite of the fact that it couldn?t have existed - in these circumstances
under the same conditions.
There is a continued repetition of such fatalistic judgments. The survey of
anarcho-syndicalist movements that occurs through chapter 3, for example, gives the
impression of both a diverse as well as reasonably consistent (in terms of general
operating principles) international tradition. What is especially absent, however, is a
consistent commentary on what particular lessons can be drawn from the specific choices
that militants made within the context of these movements. Militants, after all, were
concerned with questions of ideology, strategy, composition and structure as much as at
the movement?s inception as in its decline (as, amongst other things, the debate between
Malatesta and Monatte demonstrates). Instead of representing these choices, however, the
authors present an almost contingent vision of their own tradition, predominantly shaped
by particular national cultures of labour organisation ? ?a practice of trial and error
around a political economic core? (FFO, p.71). The failures of the French CGT or the CNT
appear pre-figured in the legacies of their domestic labour traditions.
The FORA, in particular, as the apparent synthesis of both syndicalist and specifist
approaches appears to be an immensely important case study for contemporary organisation.
This unique model of the ?anarchist organisation of workers? is, however, discussed only
briefly and only then in term of its apparent success. There is no source cited for the
claim of a membership of 100,000 but it is likely that the authors may have confused this
with the (reformist split) FORA IX. The (anarchist communist) FORA V claimed a membership
of only 10,000 at its peak (Thompson, 1990: 173-4); an issue which itself is complicated
by the unreliable figures concerning membership of both sections as well as the context of
intensive strike activity within Argentine society20. This is followed by analysis of
Arango?s (a prominent FORA theorist) rejection of society as not led by ?inexorable
economic laws? but ?ideas and ethical concepts? which is subsequently attributed as the
cause of the growth of ?anti-industrialism? within the union and the 1915 split (FFO,
p.52). This is a quite convoluted claim giving that at the heart of the 1915 split was the
effective renunciation of anarchist communism and the move to neutral syndicalism. It is
also problematic in the context of our broader tradition which has always rejected
economic determinism (most commonly associated with Marxism) in favour of a view of
history that emphasises the influence of both ideas and subjectivity while still having
class analysis at its base (see Van Der Walt and Schmidt, 2009: 83- 114).
Minority Unionism
The fatalistic conclusions drawn by the authors are at least partially rectified by their
discussion of the contemporary context of partnership with the trade unions and the
response, by sections of the IWA, to the practice of ?minority unionism?. This, however,
does raise a number of further issues. Although the authors are keen to stress
anarcho-syndicalism is still able to ?seek or achieve mass appeal? (FFO, p.70) their case
relating to the specific conditions that gave rise to mass syndicalist unions is pretty
comprehensively made and ultimately leads back to the perseverance of those factors which
determined the tradition?s decline. Minority unionism also appears (the authors may
disagree) to be a quite radical reformulation of the traditional strategies and tactics of
anarcho-syndicalism. Pouget?s original vision of an ?active minority? (FFO, p. 50) and the
experience of the FAUD and the French CGT may suggest the acceptance of a minority role as
an operating reality (although not really an aspiration). Nonetheless the tactic of
calling open, cross-organisational assemblies appears to be a quite innovative and fluid
strategy compared to, for example, the dual power role ascribed to the union, to draw on
two prominent figures, by Pouget and Rocker.
It would have been good to see more considered analysis of the contemporary conditions
that contextualise this turn beyond the pragmatic ones given of declining trade union
density and a divided labour movement (the latter of which is hardly a uniquely
contemporary phenomenon). It would have likewise been good to have some reflection on how
this presents an alternative strategy to anarcho-syndicalist unions that have attempted to
retain their mass appeal ? SAC, CNT-F and the Spanish CGT21.
The extent to which this strategy does present a turn back to the model of free assemblies
or soviets originally rejected by the CNT (FFO, p.59) is acknowledged - although the
authors do point out that a ?system of free councils? is also enshrined in the statutes of
the IWA - but not really answered satisfactorily. The authors correctly point out that
concern for the political weakness of structures has to be ultimately resolved beyond the
particular characteristics of the organs themselves - in the consciousness of the workers
and in the ability of revolutionary minorities to exercise a leadership of ideas22. These
are, however, the limits of the observations and, ultimately, in the final chapter are
re-articulated in terms of simply the need for a revolutionary union movement.
Anarcho-syndicalism in the 21st century
The book rounds off with discussion of the nature of workplace organisation in the 21st
century and a presentation of the Solidarity Federation?s vision for a revolutionary union
movement. The authors emphasise key challenges associated with the neoliberal
counter-revolution in Western Europe ? de-industrialisation, service unionism, a continued
collapse of independent working class space, dislocation of class identity and a
de-politicisation of society in general (something that has both positive and negative
connotations). There is an opportunity here to connect to a wider body of theory building
on similar themes in terms of the communisation writers. This would, however, have
possibly been superfluous to the text and generally the points are well made without the
need to bring in deeper concepts such as subsumption.
The authors make the case of the need for an independent and organised revolutionary union
against spontaneist and anti-organisational theories of struggle as well as the
rank-and-file, ?boring from within? strategies pursued by the Left in respect to the TUC
unions. They refute the case that revolutionary unions orientated towards open membership
have to be reformist. This is fair on the basis of the arguments that are made ? that
revolutionary unions will attract class conscious workers ? but doesn?t really address
what is more central to the specifist criticism in terms of the ebbs and flows of
struggle23. The state of the trade unions is analysed and their credentials as ?mass
organisations? is subject to criticism.
There follows some practical/theoretical discussion on direct action and the revolutionary
process as well as a review of the general operating principles and practices of
revolutionary unionism, largely in contrast to statist and reformist ideas. The basis of
?building the new world in the shell of the old?, the effectiveness of direct action and
the need both organisation and solidarity is all outlined (what we would probably
characterise as cultures and organisations of counter-power). These are, however,
established largely independent, or at least not principally in response to, the
challenges outlined in the previous chapter (those of the neo-liberal counterrevolution).
There is some reference to the continuity of the same methods and terrains of struggle in
spite of the fact that, ?conditions in society may vary? (FFO, p.101). This is a fair
point. There is also some discussion of casualisation and how this requires ?different
tactics and forms of struggle? (FFO, p.103). Although it is also argued that this is a
phenomenon not specifically associated with neoliberalism. More pressing issues such as
decomposition and collapse of class identity are not addressed.
Overall the extent to which anarcho-syndicalism answers the particular challenges of the
21st century is not clear. This is especially so in terms of those continuing aspects of
capitalist-state management that so effectively collapsed the anarcho-syndicalist
traditions of the 20th century. While the book finishes with a worthwhile and thoughtful
discussion of the nature of contemporary revolutionary transformation the case hasn?t
really been made that anarcho-syndicalism is especially well placed to face the challenges
associated with this task.
Concluding remarks
FFO is a step forward in terms of the general absence of a sustained culture of historical
reflection within the British anarchist milieu. While the authors do make some errors in
their representations and we are forced to question their methodological choices, the fact
that they have presented their tradition forward in this way ? an exercise so often
dismissed as ?academic? or ?navel-gazing? within the milieu ? is certainly to their
credit. FFO is also a marked improvement on the incredibly dated introductions that will
still often form the basis of the inquisitive reader?s first impressions of our movement.
Ultimately, however, the limitations of the book are reflected in the limitations of scope
within many aspects of anarchist practice in the UK. It?s time to move beyond this type of
book. We are in dire need of an honest appraisal of our tradition that draws in not just
the historical but theoretical lineage of our tradition. Anarchists forsake their theory
at their peril. We believe it is time to start forming that methodology and applying it in
practice. This is above all what anarchists need ? a methodology for the 21st century that
allows us to locate a meaningful political programme within our constructive work within
the class. Only then will social anarchism appear once more as a natural complement to the
struggles of the exploited and a beacon of hope in the face of the neoliberal onslaught.
- Collective Action
REFERENCES
Bookchin, M. (1993). "The Ghost of Anarcho-syndicalism". Anarchist
Studies, Vol. 1, Number 1.
Cahm, C. (1989) Kropotkin and the Rise of Revolutionary Anarchism, 1872 ? 1886. Cambridge
University Press.
Maurizio A. [ed.] (1907) The International Anarchist Congress, Amsterdam, 1907, translated
by Nestor McNab. Black Cat Press (2009).
Schmidt, M. and van der Walt, L. (2009) Black Flame: the revolutionary class politics of
anarchism and syndicalism. AK Press
Thompson, R. (1984) "The Limitations of Ideology in the Early Argentine Labour Movement:
Anarchism in the Trade Unions, 1890-1920". Journal of Latin American Studies 16 (1): 81?99.
Wright, S. (2002) Storming Heaven: Class Composition and struggle in Italian Autonomist
Marxism. Pluto Press.
1. V. Damier?s (2009) Anarcho-Syndicalism in the 20th Century. Black Cat Press, for
example, which is also referenced throughout, presents a more comprehensive study of the
traditions in question but more academic focus and length may be off-putting to some readers.
2.http://thecommune.co.uk/2012/12/29/fighting-for-ourselves/
3. The FARJ - Federa??o Anarquista do Rio de Janeiro ? prefer to use the terminology of
?centre-periphery? to express a critical relationship to the language of ?development?,
which express essentially imperialistic and colonial relations. The author?s continued
uses of terms such as ?developed state? are a little problematic in this respect.
4. For a better analysis of this idea see
5. We discuss the contradictions related to this in greater detail in our commentary on
the trade unions - Collective Action (2012) Worker autonomy: debate on the trade unions.
Ninth Symphony Press. http://libcom.org/blog/worker-autonomy-debate-trade-unions-15112012
6. Consider, for example, the continuation of market competition, wages and patriarchal
social organisation within many of the workers? and peasants? collectives during the
Spanish civil war. See: Subversion (1996) ?Spain 1936, the end of anarchist syndicalism??
Subversion #18
7. For example, whether the reluctance of the CNT to take power was rooted in deeper
issues concerning the possibility to transcend (aufheben) proletarian identity as the
communisation writers argue, for example, Gilles Dauv? (1998) ?When Insurrections Die ?
Quand Meurent les Insurrections. ADEL, Paris.
http://endnotes.org.uk/texts/endnotes_1/when-insurrections-die.xhtml
8. For example, Schmidt and van der Walt?s (2009) Black Flame: the revolutionary class
politics of anarchism and syndicalism. AK Press.
9. ?The conclusion arrived at by Monatte is that syndicalism is a necessary and sufficient
means for social revolution. In other words, Monatte has declared that syndicalism is
sufficient unto itself. And this is, in my opinion, a radically erroneous doctrine. The
aim of my speech is to counter this doctrine.? (Malatesta quoted in Antonelli, 1907: 121)
10. For a complete overview see: Cahm, C. (1989) Kropotkin and the rise of revolutionary
anarchism, 1872 ? 1886. Cambridge University Press.
http://libcom.org/files/cahm-kropotkin_and_the_rise_of_revolutionary_anarchism_1872-1886.pdf
Also Morris, B. (2003) Kropotkin: The Politics of Community. Humanity Books. And Zabalaza
Anarchist Communist Front (2009) Tangled Threads of Revolution: Reflections on the FdCA's
?Anarchist Communists: a Question of Class?. Zabalaza Books.
11. ?It needs another element about which Malatesta spoke and Bakunin always practised.?
Kropotkin, P. (1914) Letter to Bertoni, 2 March 1914. Internationaal Instituut voor
Sociale Geschiedenis, Amsterdam.
12. Whether certain ?anarchists? have mistakenly taken up these ideas is a slightly
different issue.
13. See Heinrich, M. (2004) An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx?s Capital.
Monthly Review Press.
http://www.scribd.com/doc/106428248/Michael-Heinrich-Alex-Locascio-An-Introduction-to-the-Three-Volumes-of-Karl-Marx-s-Capital-Monthly-Review-Press-U-S-2012
14. ?For Malatesta, therefore, any concession or negotiation under capitalism was
reformist, and so it was important for anarchists to remain ?pure?, leaving the dirty
business to others.? FFO, p.32
15. ?This association has its origin in the conviction that revolutions are never made by
individuals or even by secret societies. They make themselves; they are produced by the
force of circumstances, the movement of facts and events. They receive a long preparation
in the deep, instinctive consciousness of the masses, then they burst forth, often
seemingly triggered by trivial causes. All that a well-organized society can do is, first,
to assist at the birth of a revolution by spreading among the masses ideas which give
expression to their instincts, and to organize, not the army of the Revolution ? the
people alone should always be that army ? but a sort of revolutionary general staff,
composed of dedicated, energetic, intelligent individuals, sincere friends of the people
above all, men neither vain nor ambitious, but capable of serving as intermediaries
between the revolutionary idea and the instincts of the people.?
Bakunin, M. (1869) ?The Program of the International Brotherhood.? In: Dolgoff, S. (1971)
Bakunin on Anarchism. Black Rose Books.
16. A factor that the authors likewise identify as a critical blow against their own
tradition.
17. "The working class is the only subject which interests us. Every other form of
subjectivism is only an attempt to supplant the working class ... the problem of
militarisation therefore is completely subordinate to the development of mass struggle and
must be directed, even in its technical aspects, by the current form of the party (the
mass organisms under working-class direction) ... The military 'specific' is such only if
it refers to mass struggle. To think of the militarisation of the mass movement in terms
of von Clausewitz is worthy of fascists." (Potere Operaio quoted in Wright, 2002: 151)
18. See, for example, ?Negri?s Interrogation? In: Lotringer, S. And Marazzi, C. (2007)
Autonomia: Post-Political Politics. Intervention Series 1. Semiotext(e).
19. There is some discussion on how Solidarity Federation ?locals? are formed to address
these issues:
?The Local aims to be a hive of working class self-activity in the area, inside and
outside the union, a catalyst for workers? self-activity, an infrastructure and tool of
struggle for the working class. It?s a base not only to organise against capital and
state, but for all sorts of marginalised and oppressed groups to organise. If we?re
serious about prefiguring a libertarian communist society, we must challenge patriarchy,
racism, and bigotry of all forms within society and, when necessary, within our own ranks
too.? (FFO, p.102)
As well as reference to historical commitments to anti-racism and women?s liberation but
very little on the actual struggles themselves or how they intersect with the
socio-economic analysis outlined, e.g. how neo-liberalism has changed the terms of social
reproduction.
20. The FORA V experienced a short revival following the failed strikes of 1917 but was in
general decline following the 1915 split.
21. The CGT having been reasonably successful at this with a membership of roughly 60,000
people and representing around 2 million workers through industrial committees.
22. Although the authors do not use the term this is the basic process they describe as
the, ?anarcho-syndicalist union?s anti-capitalist and anti-state perspective are shown to
make sense? in light of the struggle. (FFO. P.67)
23. A more comprehensive outline is given by us here ? Collective Action (2012) Specifism
explained: the social and political level, organisational dualism and the anarchist
organisation.
http://libcom.org/blog/specifism-explained-social-political-level-organisational-dualism-anarchist-organisation-09
Posted By
Collective Action
Jan 21 2013 22:23
Home »
» (en) Britain, Collective Action's review of Solidarity Federation's recently published book 'Fighting for Ourselves: Anarcho-syndicalism and the class struggle'.